The Social Shaping of Technological Revolutions
Second Machine Age
Second Machine Age or Fifth Technological Revolution? (Part 6). The limits of the Brynjolfsson and McAfee policy recipes: Proposals on human capital
Second Machine Age of Fifth Technological Revolution? Different interpretations lead to different recommendations – reflections on Erik Brynjolfsson and Andrew McAfee’s book The Second Machine Age (2014)
Part Six: The limits of the Brynjolfsson and McAfee policy recipes: Proposals on human capital
What follows is the first of the concluding series of posts on Erik Brynjolfsson and Andrew McAfee’s influential book, The Second Machine Age (2014). These posts have not been intended as critique of their analysis of the new technology systems and their transformative potential; rather, my intention has been to examine how different historical understandings of technological revolutions – and of the role of markets and government – end up providing different policy guidance in the present. The series started by examining different approaches to the periodisation of industrial revolutions, and the particular differences between seeing the present moment as the start of a Second Machine Age, as Brynjolfsson and McAfee hold, or as the midpoint of the fifth revolution, as I understand it. I then discussed the patterns of repetition identified by the Neo-Schumpeterians in the diffusion of successive revolutions. Then post 3 analysed the profound nature of the transition we are going through, while post 4 focused on how what Brynjolfsson and McAfee call ‘bounty’ (leading to growth) and ‘spread’ (leading to inequality), have repeatedly occurred in the process of creative destruction’ that has characterised such major shifts. Finally, in post 5 argued for the importance of understanding the role of socio-political shaping over technological determinism; the wide range of the viable provided by each new paradigm; and the subsequent possibility – and indeed necessity – for government to set a congruent and synergistic direction for ‘the market’ (or markets) to function in a positive-sum game between business and society. It is now time to examine Brynjolfsson and McAfee’s policy prescriptions in the light of the richer understanding of the social assimilation of technological revolutions proposed in this series. After a general assessment of the limited nature of their proposals, this post will begin the final series of four, dedicated to discussing their recommendations.
– – – – –
Introduction: The limits of Brynjolfsson and McAfee’s policy recipes
Most of The Second Machine Age focuses on describing current and future technical change, accompanied by warnings about its speed, depth and worrying social consequences. From the potential of robotics and artificial intelligence (AI) to decimate jobs for humans to the multiple negative effects of increasing inequality, Brynjolfsson and McAfee share the concerns of all those who care about our socio-economic future, from those focused primarily on economic growth in general to those campaigning for social justice. The surprise comes on discovering that, after such a vivid, complex and, to an extent, apocalyptic rendering of the future, the two chapters dedicated to meeting and mitigating this future put forward policy recommendations that are timid in scope and surprisingly divorced from the technologies that they depict so well.
The authors themselves admit the modesty of their suggestions. At the end of ‘Policy Recommendations’, in the chapter that specifically looks at the government actions to apply, they note:
“The policy recommendations we outline above share one simple and modest goal: bringing about higher rates of overall economic growth. If this happens, the prospects of workers and job seekers alike will improve.” (p. 227).
They are, of course, working from a premise which I have spent the past three posts [here, here and here] contesting: that the dwindling employment and increasing inequality brought by the technologies which they describe as ‘spread’ will inevitably remain into the future, and that the changes to the fundamental structure of unequal income distribution can be expected to be permanent (Ch. 9). Taking that as a given, many of their recommendations are only ways to temper such enduring changes. So, while there is nothing wrong with their statement that if growth happens ‘the prospects of workers and job seekers alike will improve’ (p. 228), it is disappointing that they cannot move beyond standard economic orthodoxy, when advancing policies for growth, and that they do not dare think out-of-the-box to define a future that will benefit all, given the major changes in technology.
Instead, in search of new solutions for the future, Brynjolfsson and McAfee go back to the tired pure market theories of the ‘Economics 101’ textbooks. They are extremely cautious about taking an interventionist approach, tentatively advocating ‘government policies … in a few key areas’ (p. 208), while claiming that, right or left, economists share more common ground than the media leads us to believe. Such caution and reliance on existing formulas is understandable if all you want is to gather as much of elite opinion as possible around non-controversial proposals. Consensus is indeed important, but it is only worth the effort if it is around effective policies.
Yet, the uniqueness of each new technological paradigm requires a public policy response that is fundamentally different each time. And here we see perhaps the most short-sighted result of applying the Economics 101 prescriptions: as Robert Solow famously noted, dominant economic theory ignores the role of technological change. Engineers should be the first to reject this blind spot, and yet they claim that:
“…many of the things that we should do in a time of brilliant technologies are not related to the technologies themselves. Instead, they’re about promoting growth and opportunities more generally” (p. 208).